Sylvain Poirier (settheory.net)
Abstract. A version of the growing block theory of time is developed based on the choice of both consciousness and mathematics as fundamental substances, while dismissing the reality/semantics distinction usually assumed by works on time theory. The well-analyzable growing block structure of mathematical ontology revealed by mathematical logic, is used as a model for a possible deeper working of conscious time. Physical reality is explained as emerging from a combination of both substances, with a proposed specific version of the Consciousness Causes Collapse interpretation. This leads to new solutions to old problems, including the epistemic problem and issues with Relativity.
Keywords Growing Block - Mathematical Platonism - Mathematical Logic - Foundations of physics - Libertarian free will - von Neumann-Wigner interpretation.
This article will defend the coherence of a growing block universe theory of time,
by describing a detailed version of it
where its old problems appear to find natural solutions.
This independently
develops by other aspects, the concepts first introduced in
the FQXI essay on mind/mathematics dualism (settheory.net/mind-math_dualism.pdf).
See also the pages on the interpretations of quantum physics
(settheory.net/physics).
The writing of this article started as a reaction to some related existing
philosophical works on time theory, until a more extensive literature review
was undertaken to feed more sections.
The first sections so written, pertaining more to the general flaws of academic
philosophy than to the specific topic of time theory, were then moved as an
addition to a previously written page on such generalities
(antispirituality.net/philosophy).
This left here the following on-topic sections:
Section 1 argues that, for diverse physical reasons, a growing
block view would be at odds with physicalism.
Section 2 briefly explains the growing block time order in
mathematical reality revealed by mathematical logic, and announces
its use as a model to better understand conscious time.
Section 3 starts applying this methodology by expressing this time
structure in precise terms. Semantics appears as a real creative
process.
Section 4 argues against the metaphysical concept of doomsday by
pointing out why any reality relies on some potential future.
Section 5 describes the existing draft images of possible futures
for mathematical reality.
Section 6 infers from articulations of the possible and the
actual, a perspective on free will and divisions of consciousness
into individuals.
Section 7 analyzes the epistemic objection, and invites to revise
the concepts of time, presentness and their physical details, to
provide a new solution and better fit relativistic invariance.
Section 8 argues the impossibility of time loops, and clarifies
the structure of black holes to refute the presence of a Gödelian
region inside.
Section 9 offers an account of physical reality and the nature of
physical time, as emerging from a combination of consciousness and
mathematics.
Section 10 defends the physical place of free will by critically
reviewing usual arguments against the role of consciousness in
quantum physics, and providing some last clarifications.
Finally, section 11 invites to a Bayesian approach to compare the
plausibilities of competing metaphysics.
(I submitted this article in the beginning of March 2022
to the one journal which seemed appropriate, with 3 criteria : on-topic
(metaphysics and hard sciences), open-access without fees, and accepting
articles of this size a bit long. About 6 weeks later, in lack of reply,
I inquired and learned that the editorial board was under restructuration, thus
not ready to accept submissions at the moment. I then gave up
and just sent it to
Philarchive instead.)
Third, only a non-physical consciousness outside space-time can escape "the difficulties caused by the approximate and ill-defined nature of decoherence" (Wallace 2007:40) (which is emergent, non-unique and progressive with no definite instant measure of its progress) to effectively see it as a completed process and use it as a condition for collapse.
This condition on a given collapse ensures the next outcome will
stay "compatible" (non-orthogonal) with the previous one. Put as a
general rule, it gives a non-destructive growing-block form to the
perceptions history: collapses come as updates of a state of the
universe defined from the growing block of past perceptions. This
GBT structure is already well-known under labels of "no-collapse"
interpretations: "relative state" (Everett 1957), "single mind",
"many minds", or "relational" (Barrett 2018; Soltau's articles and
references).
Equivalently, the resulting history stays among MW's reality
branches. Thus, it inherits its (very subtle) exact respect of
energy conservation, needed for compatibility with General
Relativity, which time-local laws involved in OC are unlikely to
fulfill (facing troubles defining energy in limited time for
non-isolated systems).
Then, philosophers trying to defend GBT over rival time theories contradict physicalism in two ways.
First, the recognition of intuition as a legitimate source of
insights on the nature of time, is a spiritualist position : how
could a consciousness emerging from effects of well-known physical
laws which rather fit eternalism, experience an objective time
hidden at a more fundamental reality layer ?
Finally, physicalism combined with the locality of physical laws, makes GBT indistinguishable from Presentism. Indeed, given 3 times t<t'<t", it is ineffective to qualify the events at t as existing for those at t", because events at t" cannot access them due to shielding by the layer of events around t'. Only an indirect, encrypted trace of the events at t can cross this layer, with possible permanent information loss.
Accepting spiritualism (like GBT founders Bergson and
Whitehead), more details are needed. Both traditional versions are
mind/matter dualism and idealism. I will explore a new option :
taking mathematics as the other primitive substance, then
explaining the physical as emerging from their combination. This
is motivated as follows.
Mathematical Platonism sees mathematical systems as having an
independent, timeless reality (the understanding of which usually
makes one a mathematician rather than a philosopher). Let us
express it as:
However, a deep understanding of mathematical logic, developed in
settheory.net (especially philosophical
complements and more in a new text),
leads to modify this, rejecting 3.:
mathematical existence, though independent of our time,
has its own GBT structure. Indeed, the necessary architecture of
the foundations of mathematics has intuitive similarities with our
time, thus can appear more familiar once clothed by the vocabulary
and intuition of time.
Here are short hints. Discovering the necessities of mathematical
ontology, is a matter of not postulating anything arbitrarily.
Mathematics needs expressions. Any meaningful expression (except
tensorial ones) has a hierarchy of sub-expressions, representing
the time order along which these can take values. To describe
expressions and their semantics, requires first-order logic and
model theory. But model theory, like all mathematics, also
requires set theory as a foundation.
Then, endlessly many versions of set theory appear possible.
Anyway we must not choose, but accept all reasonable ones.
Generally, a mathematical time structure is the transitive closure
of a given well-founded relation. While sub-expressions were
partially ordered, ordinals form a total time order through all
time scales, from finite steps, to large cardinals towards the end
of eternity. The strength hierarchy of set theories,
starting with Finite Set Theory, tracks the largest time scales.
We shall now re-use this analogy for the inverse purpose : using
known features of mathematical ontology as a working model to
approach consciousness. For this, some facts of mathematical logic
clothed by a time language will be used as tentative descriptions
of hidden aspects of conscious ontology. Yet for example, I
consider the features of perfect symmetries and identical copies
as specific to mathematics.
On the way, spiritual sources of hints such as the Seth Material will clarify strange aspects, confirming bold mathematical insights and inspiring new candidate solutions to old problems (while the physical, as an emerging reality, will illustrate the picture but cannot probe the foundations).
Such differences between appearances and deeper realities of conscious ontology, can be explained by biases from specific limitations of physical (human) life; beyond this life, some other forms of time experience are possible.
Let us dive into this metaphorical mix of times, or experience of
mathematical time by the study of mathematical logic (hopefully
more objective than usual time experience).
By definition, "the past" means the universe of all things, i.e.
events, which currently happen to exist as available objects of
meaningful discourse : those we can remember.
We say that A precedes B if B remembers A,
thus if A is a part of B, needed to account for B's
creation. This relation is naturally transitive (or anyway its
transitive closure can be restored by digging a little): if C
remembers B which remembers A, then C
indirectly remembers A.
An expression with proper syntax to be interpretable, is either
Then, it needs a semantics. Now comes a crucial point : semantics
is a creation process like any other, and thus a possible
model to understand the nature of all creation processes. It
creates an interpretation, usually called a token,
of a given expression.
The memory of a token, is the range of all objects it
involves : the values it gives to all variables, either free or
bound by quantifiers. Like any event, a token cannot belong to its
own memory: its "creation time" escapes its past (section 8).
Re-applying semantics to an already interpreted open expression,
will probably create a new token, with a larger memory. But,
re-interpreting a bounded expression only restores an old token;
then, semantics is no more creative, thus somehow, "the past is
dead". If you remember having made an operation, then you will be
bored repeating it.
Some arguments in the literature (Loss 2019) are concerned with
GBT's inability to express doomsday. While this should not matter
(Callender 2011a), another reply is possible. The possibility of a
doomsday relies on the contingency of the physical, whose laws may
not ensure the existence of a physical future (space-time
extension). While the mentioned risk of Big Crunch is ruled out
since 1998 (Wikipedia: Cosmological constant), others not
mentioned remain (falling in a black hole; speculatively, a false
vacuum decay, or a cancellation of reality branch in the Slow
Collapse interpretation). However, these no more count as
metaphysical doomsdays when rejecting physicalism to see time as a
feature of consciousness, whose existence is more fundamental than
matter.
Now, mathematical time cannot stop: a present event that "is" will necessarily become a past one that "exists". The existence of x, defined by the existential formula (∃y, y=x), is its role of object that can be named, irreversible expression of its reality. A definition is a form of tokening, naming the operational role of an expression by a new symbol, thus giving it existence; the general theory of semantics can describe any token, seeing it as past, thus giving it a future.
Oddly somehow, the future is the foundation of the past: to
describe things, one needs to be in their future. Research takes
time. The better we wish to understand events and why they
occurred, and to elucidate this understanding, the more time it
takes.
Mathematical logic reflects this as follows. By Tarski's Undefinability theorem, a "present" time only able to token any chosen expression about the past, is too short to define the infinite set of all tokens of possible expressions; this definition can only be tokened later, once all those tokens occurred and appear as past.
The strengths of set theories in terms of higher infinities
(faraway futures), affect the ranges of arithmetical theorems
(facts on the past) they can prove (understand). Thus, when trying
to build a model of set theory on top of a non-standard model of
arithmetic, the construction may run for a while across some
non-standard ordinal hierarchy, until, at any later "time"
(non-standard ordinal) without describable limit (large cardinal),
it suddenly breaks by uncovering its nonstandardness.
Then, "claims about the future" can be given the substitute
meaning of being true in them all, which (by the Completeness
theorem) is equivalent to provability: the "truth" of such a claim
means its provability given the current state of affairs. As
finite systems, proofs may be found and checked faster than the
actual unfolding of events (which may involve actual infinity).
Another article by the same authors (2017) argues that GBT is incompatible with Humean Supervenience. Let us check their premises :
"9. There are not irreducible necessary connections between distinct existents (8, definition of Humean Supervenience)."
Take two times t<t', and distinct existents:
That their necessary connection may contradict Humeanism, will
not be my point. I doubt its irreducibility, which did not seem
clearly defined there. Another premise is
"4. If some propositions about the future are made true by something (or things) not in the future, then there are irreducible necessary connections between distinct existents".
The truth of a genuine proposition may have an irreducible
necessary connection with its objects, as its token remembers
them. However, our only meaningful "propositions about the future"
are formed by emulation systems seeing them as abbreviating other
propositions about either ersatz worlds or provability. In the
provability case, the future tensed proposition P "about A"
abbreviates a proposition about B. This is a syntactic
connection of a familiar pseudo-proposition with a proper one. I
also doubt its irreducibility, but more worryingly, its ability to
connect A with B.
Tokening P over ersatz worlds, would connect its truth
with A just through the copy of A in that ersatz
world which will become actual, by the way they postulated ersatz
worlds to work. In mathematics however, no ersatz world can become
actual: the unfolding actual world will appear only approximated
by some pre-existing ersatz worlds; it is genuinely created in the
(potential) topological closure of their range. It differs from
them neither in substance nor ontology, but only in quality : a
"real" world is a standard one.
Intuitively, standardness is a kind of fullness, and equivalent
to a kind of compatibility with endless, indescribably remote
futures, as mentioned above. This ultimate quality cannot be
anticipated nor formalized; it cannot be fully proven in finite
time, but only eventually refuted. Any unfolding process is anyway
a necessary part of any process of understanding its own full
details.
Ersatz worlds are illustrated by Christian Sundberg's testimony
repeated in diverse videos. Similarly, the Seth Material pictures
evolution as going from the fuzziness of foreseen probable futures
to the precision of their actualized versions (Roberts 1970 &
1979). Other excerpts mention "probabilities systems" featuring no
clear linear ordering nor real vs ersatz distinction (Roberts
1972: 91), which I would compare with the study of other
mathematical theories, where standardness does not apply.
These mathematical concepts of actuality and pre-existing
possibilities, whose irreducible mysteriousness (standardness is
undefinable, while all models of set theory are non-algorithmic)
do not undermine their reality, can shed light on their conscious
versions, ingredients of free will.
Both mathematical logic and the Seth material indicate that possibilities far exceed what can be actualized at a time, and any actualization creates even more new possibilities than it uses. In mathematics, the explosive indiscriminate actualization of all appearing possibilities into an inextricable mess is expressed by set theories; but consciousness needs to care selecting opportunities to optimize its development.
A version of this preference problem is featured by proof theory
(whose finitism makes the standardness concept inapplicable).
Indeed, from any given axiomatic theory, an explosive range of
possible deductions appears, but not all are equally worthy: some
statements (conjectures) appear as more valuable goals of
deductive exploration, for which some possible short term
deductions are more likely to be useful. Then, strategies are
needed to make creative works more efficient towards given goals.
Yet, their efficiency is often unpredictable: the only reliable
way to find the shortest proof may be to try them all (or a huge
amount of them), but that exploration would give up the concern
for which shorter proofs were desired in the first place.
Then, the division of consciousness into individuals may come as
a parallel undertaking of multiple exploration strategies, each
protected from the cost and distracting noise of others. This
division needs to be balanced with connections sharing the
benefits of findings across individuals. For example, someone can
benefit being directly given the shortest proof from someone
else's extensive search, while ignoring the fruitless parts of
that search.
Since any choice is a kind of determination, the meaning of
alternative possibilities needs clarification. Even determinism
cannot mean full predictability: any complete "prediction" would
be a real action encompassing the described events, and likely to
disturb them away from their predicted course, thus obsolete. But
free will brings the following differences:
GBT suffers this famous paradox: people's time intuition it
relies on, includes the conviction of "living in some objective
present", which is going to be false, like such beliefs held in
the past which mistakenly subsist.
New answers will be provided. First, the geometrical definition
of "the present" as the edge of existing space-time, tied with
physicalism, is rejected. Then, the concept of "living in the
present" needs a legitimate syntax. Let us first analyze "This
just happened", or more formally
(P) "There is hardly anything more than what this remembers".
This still displays an unnoticed oddity of presentness : its negative form. It expresses a disbelief in the existence of later events than remembered ones. So, the paradox would be past people's mistaken disbeliefs.
Most people admit the possible existence of life on other
planets, thus of many events they cannot remember, as these took
place elsewhere. So, reading (P) literally, they correctly
believe that they are not living in the present. To
distinguish claims, would require sorting unremembered events by
the filter of "being consecutive to this"; that would be so
complicated.
Mathematical logic has no concept of "objective present". Its time is purely relational, like in eternalism. Any token gives to the variables under open quantification, the range it happens to remember. Beyond specifying an event's memory, there is no sense asking when it occurred.
It has no objective simultaneity concept either (but tolerates conventional ones, such as the cumulative hierarchy and the constructible hierarchy, while a more objective one may emerge at large time scales where anything could collect a memory of everything else). Like in Relativity, "independence or equality" is not transitive.
Indeed, how can any fact about the present, exist and then get
destroyed ? More precisely from previous insights:
Yet, the eternalistic concept of complete totality is rejected:
The Seth material, such as (Roberts 1970; Roberts 1972: 117-118
& Ch. XVI), describes physical reality by combining CC with
MW, where only some of the possible reality branches from MW get
actualized by free will. An absolute simultaneity appears partly
defined, leaving the question of its full definiteness unclear.
Interstellar psychic travel, not limited by the speed of light, is
likened to travel between reality branches. I will try clarifying
things by an example.
Consider two planets A and B in different
galaxies. At one point, the time line of A splits into two
branches A1 and A2, while
that of B doesn't (its other branches are independent of A,
thus can be ignored). Then, simultaneity can relate a time tB
on B, a time t1 on A1
and a time t2 on A2, where t1
and t2 can be physically quite different. This
way, simultaneity between two planets is relative to the choice of
a reality branch on each (only having to stay space-like to belong
a common reality, while "reference frames" are mere artifacts of
mathematical formalization). This can be expressed in terms of an
hyper-time along which reality grows, but forming a mere partial
order, and inessential to the actual processes: subjective time
can run "at different speeds" with respect to it, leaving such
"speed" differences unnoticed.
Indeed, consider the twin paradox in Relativity. The physical
time interval between events of separating and meeting again,
differs between twins. Now, if subjective time experience is
relativistic invariant (following physical time, not usable as a
non-physical instrument to measure absolute speed or gravitational
potential), then it cannot measure any interval of hyper-time from
a given past event.
Finally, let us seriously answer the epistemic objection by
conceiving "the present" as a matter of focus. Generally, focus
is a choice of specific memory with which an action is processed.
For semantics, it is a choice of ranges for the quantified
variables.
So, "living in the present" is an act of focus on our "immediate
past", from which some consecutive events will follow. There is no
question of when that "immediate past" really occurred, nor when
the results will follow, as hyper-time cannot be measured. It is
just necessary that results will follow.
To question the "validity" of this experience, requires to
re-interpret it. However, this interpretation is not a matter of
reading simple words, but of restoring a focus on this experience,
similar to its own original focus. Humans seem unable to do that.
Now, for anyone with this power, this action can lead to 3
possible results, illustrated by different excerpts of the Seth
material:
Then, compared to generally possible conscious experience, physical life appears singular by its rule of "focus on the present", which seemingly forms a single time thread (a body's physical extension) by always perceiving "the immediate past" much stronger, while quantum decoherence turns different choices of measurement results into separate, physically non-interacting "reality branches".
In this framework, only two physically effective psychic time
travel models appear acceptable : one, between differently aged
co-existing reality branches; the other, by creating a new branch
from a past event. Existing reality branches persist. In a worst
case scenario (Roberts 1972: ch. XV) anticipating quantum
immortality (Squires 1986), a civilization which destroyed its
planet may "reincarnate" in a parallel reality where they avoid
destruction.
Conscious ontology can depart from our linear time structure;
mystical experiences of timelessness should be no surprise when
most mathematicians keep an eternalistic view of mathematical
reality. Yet, time loops locally similar to our time, or any
memory loops, cannot occur:
This does not affect quantum gravity, whose relevant time scales
are not related with conscious times.
I will reply the challenge "to offer an explanation of why a Gödelian world is not possible" (Le Bihan 2014), by refuting arguments for its possibility.
Writing down Gödelian metrics does not prove their physical
possibility, any better than writing inconsistent theories could
prove the existence of incoherently described mathematical
structures.
The big bang is our only example of space-time not visibly coming
from a dynamical evolution. It came without time loop, and nothing
suggests it could have been otherwise. So, to argue that a
Gödelian region can appear, requires a dynamical creation
scenario.
The main candidate scenario may be the collapse of matter into a
rotating black hole. Precisely, in the Kerr-Newman metric (Wikipedia) of a black hole, any
time loop must meet one defined by ϕ being the only
variable coordinate. This requires the coefficient of dϕ2
in the metric to change sign, namely that (r2+a2)(r2+a2cos2θ)
+ a2sin2θ(rrs−rQ2)
turns negative. This only happens near the ring singularity (r≃0,
cos θ≃0) with an electric charge (rQ≠0).
Then, the whole region below the inner event horizon would be
Gödelian, as a time loop can be drawn from any point by first
moving down to near the ring singularity, then following it
(backwards to the rotation) until t decreases enough
before going back up.
But, just expressing a metric satisfying the field equations,
does not mean physical space-time will follow it. The stability
condition for convergence to this solution breaks at the inner
event horizon, where material density suddenly diverges
(Carballo-Rubio et al. 2021 ; Hamilton 2018; Hamilton &
McMaken 2021), forming a wall of infinite energy abruptly ending
space-time.
Inside a black hole, the external time coordinate t
locally acts as space. Local time is directed by the r
coordinate (intuitively the altitude, as oblate spheroids with
equation r=constant are roughly of size r),
decreasing from rH+ at the outer
horizon (no return limit), to rH- at
the inner horizon which locally appears as 2 fronts (surfaces)
coming at light speed from different directions, and colliding:
the lower front (r=rH-, t=-∞)
usually called "ingoing", comes "from the bottom" ; the upper one
(r=rH-, t=+∞), or "outgoing", comes "from the top".
Objects falling to the upper front contribute to the increase of rH-; those falling to the lower front contribute to its decrease. By symmetry, both cases can be represented by the same figure.
Green lines represent r; their black asymptotes are the fronts; dotted lines represent t; the falling object is blue; red and orange hyperbola branches, outside space-time, illustrate the figure's geometry : the object shifts the fronts orthogonally to it.
Actually, the lower front is the concentrated appearance of the matter which formed the black hole all the way from its birth, precisely all the part of it which fell on its upper front, thus contributing to its current size ; similarly, the upper front is the concentrated view of all the matter which will later fall on its lower front. (As the figure shows, any matter coming from the side of t one is approaching, to any target, shrinks the delay to one's collision with remaining front layers, compared to the front's location defined from empty space.)
Crossing a material layer gives an impulse to collapse in both
lateral dimensions. The figure shows it with roles reversed: the
front meeting the object then starts a decrease of r
before colliding the other front. The closer to light speed a
layer in it goes, the more sudden it feels this decrease.
This collapse (decrease of r) goes on across the
successive infinitesimal layers of the front made of the matter
which fell at successive ages of the black hole's history, and
which similarly got those values of r as decreasing
fractions of their respective rH-,
being shot at increasingly collapsed stages by the same process.
The inner horizon of a black hole newly formed from a collapsing
star is roughly similar, with its "north upper" and "south upper"
fronts colliding onto the equatorial plane like a balloon
collapses to the shape of a pancake (interrupting an incomplete
material collapse if rH->0). Seen
from other ages, this "birth stage" layer in the lower front is
followed by more layers, of matter coming from all ages from this
birth to the end of t on the opposite hemisphere.
So, no chance appears to escape anywhere beyond that firewall; for the same reason, "wormholes" conceived as slightly modified black holes cannot be traversed, while those requiring huge negative masses are ruled out by thermodynamics in QFT. Finally, if nothing can reach a Gödelian region, then nothing can create one either.
The above risk of mistake illustrates a genuine division of
physics in two kinds (orthogonal to the GR/QM division) treating
physical time differently, which appears natural if physical
reality emerges from of a combination of consciousness and
mathematics, and physics is its mathematical component:
To explain the role of theoretical physics, think of Euclidean
geometry as a toy model. Like any mathematical theory, its syntax
is made of finite systems, and has time orders, such as that of
any successive deductions of theorems from its axioms. Unlike
arithmetic and set theory, its semantics lacks a genuine time
structure, a fact usually seen as supporting eternalism.
Yet, its other features of continuous symmetries and actual infinity are seldom read metaphysically. Indeed, physics describes information as locally finite by mathematics with a continuous semantics, even for the smallest information unit (the qbit). This contradiction between mathematical and intended semantics is unsurprising when mathematically describing a reality with a non-mathematical ontology (type of existence with structured contingencies).
Consider a space-time region with a "past" side and a "future"
side. To each side is given some configuration space
representing the possible states of systems there, respectively
called "initial states" and "final states". Then, theoretical
physics defines a time symmetric correspondence between both. Each
physical theory defines these "configuration space" and
"correspondence" precisely.
Dynamical physics introduces a causal view of this
correspondence, ignored by theoretical physics. It proceeds by
picking an initial state, then computing its impact on the future
side. A physicist doing this may be imitating a process from
another layer of consciousness, by which perceptions create
physical reality. Hence the practical match between physical and
computational times, absent from theoretical physics.
The numerical analysis algorithms for dynamical physics usually appear much more complex and unnatural than the abstract expression of the theoretical physics so processed. Yet, they must exist, and let in principle any effect be related, at any accuracy level, to a finite lot of distinct causes (approximating states by finite amounts of information), for physics to play its role of defining the kind of causality laws needed to form a proper universe.
The dynamical treatment of General Relativity brings time
asymmetries and irreversibilities absent from its main equations:
Quantum theory provides an evolution operator U mapping any initial state |ψ〉 to a final state U|ψ〉. From any initial state |ψ〉 and any final state |ψ'〉, it defines a number p = |〈ψ'|U|ψ〉|2 ∈ [0,1]. As p may depend on endlessly complex contexts, the continuity of its range [0,1] expresses the continuity of the semantics of quantum theory as a mathematical theory.
Then, its dynamical mode claims : "If the system was last found
in initial state |ψ〉, the probably to find its final state
as |ψ'〉 if measured in that sense is p". Here, the
ambiguous and paradoxical concept of "probability" bridges the
continuous and deterministic mathematical semantics of theoretical
physics, to time asymmetric ontological claims of randomness for
discrete physical possibilities, made effectively law-like
(predictive) independently of actual mathematical infinities, by
admitting computable approximations (while giving to computable
facts a quantum complexity measure differing from classical
complexity).
In a presence of time loops, quantum theory would respond (if it responds, which becomes questionable with a non-trivial first de Rham cohomology group, often involved by time loops, because of possible issues with gauge invariance when electric charges are allowed along such loops) by having the sum of its p over an exhaustive list of distinguishable final states, turn out to differ from 1 (on which it otherwise sticks), most likely with extremely low or large values. In clear, quantum theory ignores ontology, but a good ontology should exclude time loops in order for physical "probabilities" to be taken ontologically seriously (yet not too seriously as we shall explain).
The consciousness side of this metaphysics is known as cosmic
idealism (Kastrup 2017 ; Chalmers 2017), specified with our
GBT structure. Physical perceptions are a part of the block of
conscious experience. A physical reality branch selected from
these and abstracted from all other qualia than those felt by a
Great Mathematician, defines a physical state (density operator).
New perceptions update it as "wavefunction collapse", taking foot
among the times of quantum decoherence (aspect of entropy
creation) which emerge by quantum thermodynamics, only
vaguely following physical times.
This ability of consciousness to collapse physical states, is no
more mysterious than the possibility for these mathematical
objects to exist beyond mathematics, as objects of perceptions.
Both acts of perceiving and updating physical states (mathematical
shadows of blocks of perceptions) are the same, and the chicken
and the egg of each other.
This CC version uses MW as its zombie world. The claimed failure of the zombie argument (Mohammadian 2021) vanishes since "collapse does not occur" and "collapse occurs uncaused" respectively expressing the "bare theory" and "branching" descriptions of MW, do not differ empirically. The concept of "physical difference" makes no sense by lack of a physical substance, whose role is played by mathematical objects under conscious focus, and "collapse" only makes a subjective difference by moving the focus.
Finally, the physical can be understood as having a conceptual nature : mathematical concepts of timeless continuous systems and symmetries, induce formal evolution rules for discrete and time ordered physical states. Actually in mathematical reality, syntax and semantics are on par: the syntax may explain the semantics as well as the other way round.
This resembles the role of set theory as a source of truths on
arithmetic. The criterion of set theoretical provability for the
truth of arithmetical formulas, can be expressed as an algorithm,
which will look complex and arbitrary. Then, to validate this
algorithm as a genuine truth criterion, namely to believe the
formulas so checked, involves making sense of set theory with its
concepts of infinity.
Our last two sections will examine the lack of proper reason for the unpopularity of CC (Arroyo 2020: ch.6). The only good excuse (Arroyo 2022: 3.2.3), is the lack of a famous clear and suitable expression of CC to argue about.
"...philosophers reject interactionism on largely physical grounds... while physicists reject an interactionist interpretation of QM on largely philosophical grounds... This sort of interpretation needs to be formulated in detail to be assessed... Only Stapp goes into much detail, with an interesting but somewhat idiosyncratic account" (Chalmers 2003: pp.31-32)
Kastrup (2017 & 2019) gave good arguments for CC, as
recognized by (Sepetyi 2018), who still could not see the
advantages of cosmic idealism, left unclear by Kastrup's tentative
expression in another article.
The decoherence pre-condition for collapse, defended here, only
appears elsewhere as implied by different interpretations : London
& Bauer's "Consciousness recognizes the collapse" (Arroyo
2020: ch.7); "single-mind" and "many-minds" in (Barrett 2006)
which supports these with strong arguments (ignored in Barrett's
later article, maybe due to the oddity of such Mind Makes No
Collapse interpretations).
It leaves "random outcomes" as the only avatar of free will by
ruling out the role of other quantum effects. This non-literal
reading of "randomness" is considered by some authors (Durieux
2021) and micro-PK experimentalists (Burns 2012), but leaves
others shy or doubtful (Runyan 2018; Stapp).
The philosophical consensus stays disconnected from modern
science, either dreaming of quantum gravity, or exploiting the
artifacts of non-relativistic QM as basis for metaphysical
debates, leaving to future physicists the subordinate task of
extending to QFT the validity of this non-relativistic discourse.
Remaining debaters about CC are even more direly left to float
free from science and reason: aside caricatural trends of academic
philosophy (Callender 2011b; Bryant 2020), flaws remain pervasive,
when calling "arguments":
Some philosophers even try to justify their infamous (Arenhart
2019) "floating free from physics" (Arroyo & Arenhart 2020):
Once 2. is rejected, facts 3. and 4. miss a legitimacy.
Discussions on topics like free will or Hempel's dilemma, stay
hopeless by not clarifying if expected substances, structures,
properties, laws, ontologies or explanations are meant to be
mathematical (either finite or infinite), or how they articulate
with such (as if disbelief in mathematical Platonism could excuse
this silence).
The vacuity of usual physicalist arguments is widely recognized
(Diley 2004; Lycan 2009; Rodrigues 2014; Smythe 2017; Goetz 2021;
Bennett 2021). Some physicalists like Bennett here, challenge
spiritualists to describe minds like physical systems, by any
mathematical laws or quasi-mathematical forms of understanding
suitable to their brain. Some spiritualists have the weakness of
endorsing that duty (Hoffman 2018; Chalmers 2021), missing the
spiritualism which answers "Can you mathematically describe
consciousness" by "No". As we saw, this answer does not prevent
understanding and investigation.
Many scientists in the debate don't understand QM. The widely referenced claimed experimental refutation of CC is ridiculous nonsense (Reason 2017).
According to engineers Malozemoff & Mroczkowski (2019),
"quantum collapse is now understood to be able to occur without a
conscious human observer". Indeed, conscious animal or ghost
observers should suffice (hardly anyone sees afterlife as an
exclusivity of humans). Seriously, they present OC as the
generally accepted understanding of physicists, though OC is
neither widely accepted, nor anyhow understood by lack of a QFT
version. They misrepresent science in other ways (van Lommel
2019).
Vervoort (2020) argues "the possibility of an immaterial substance choosing among quantum states— contradicts one of the most fundamental laws of nature, namely the energy conservation principle". Now, if this law is fatal to any interpretation violating it, then the dead one is OC, leaving after-decoherence CC safe with less competition. He first insisted that "Spike currents are constituted of the combination of many thousands of (...) ionic currents [which are] stochastic” (2.1), which "corresponds to classical randomness... usually seen as deriving from deterministic, even if unpredictable, processes."(2.4)
This widespread misconception of thermal randomness has both historical and philosophical roots : Statistical Mechanics (SM) was first expressed by Boltzmann on classical foundations (BSM), later superseded by Gibb's approach (GSM), but kept as the reference by philosophers protecting their physicalism from the challenges of modern physics, by a Good Bye, Lenin! attitude to the quantum revolution.
For example, Anta (2021) who "Due to extension reasons...will focus exclusively on classical statistical mechanics, and not on its quantum counterpart" (footnote 1), presents SM as "a counterexample to Hempel's symmetry thesis, where the predictive capacity of a theory is directly correlated with its explanatory potential", so as "to understand in depth why [GSM] is hegemonic within real predictive practices... and [BSM] is constantly claimed in philosophical domains... for its conceptual coherence in providing explanations" (p. 418), like the highly predictive parents-giving theory of Christmas presents is hegemonic among adults, while children prefer the more powerful Santa Claus explanation:Here, Wallace (2020) was expressing the misconception he meant to
refute, not only tediously in that article "under the (of
course false) assumption that the underlying microphysics is
classical mechanics... to make contact with the contemporary
literature rather than out of a belief that quantum theory is
irrelevant here", but also radically based on QM, briefly "at
the end (section 12)", and more fully in his previous
article (2016b) showing that "statistical-mechanical
probabilities reduce entirely to quantum-mechanical ones".
So, Gibbs distributions come as the limits of quantum states (the
real microstates) in the SM classical limit of QM; the meaning of
their probabilistic syntax is a matter of interpreting QM.
Standard interpretations (Copenhagen, MW, Qbism, CC) give GSM as
their classical limits. Others (HV, OC...) don't, but still cannot
match BSM anyway.
Considering an SM system with a detector giving some random
output, let us compare diverse interpretations. In standard QM
interpretations, this output is created by measurement.
In BSM, it is extracted from an infinite pool of pre-existing
data : the decimals of coordinates of the initial configuration.
So, this output will be as truly random as this data pool was, and
more precisely an absolute mystery by lack of any law specifying
where this pool might come from. This big question mark stands as
the usual definition of "determinism". Yet, authors exist who
question this definition and explore other interpretations of
classical SM (Del Santo 2020).
Another conceivable interpretation of SM consists in a computer
simulation of a supposedly isolated system. The computer's memory
limits will let random outputs become pseudo-random after a while.
This interpretation has two unrealistic aspects: its
coarse-graining forms an empirically unsupported asymmetry; and
natural systems are not isolated. A more realistic simulation
requires infinitely many computers working in parallel to describe
respective regions in the universe. Finally, the output will be as
random as its source: the infinite pool of initial data
distributed across this infinity of computers, that is precisely a
total mystery by lack of any law specifying it.
Like with QM, all such interpretations of SM are empirically
equivalent. Thus, experimentalists could pick any interpretation,
including a big question mark, to succeed. Yet, troubles come when
proclaiming that they got the right metaphysics by Hempel's
symmetry, while they did not start analyzing and comparing
interpretations in the light of QM.
The brain's chaotic evolution f from states x
defined near Heisenberg inequalities scales, through thermal
fluctuations, up to macro-outcomes y=f(x)
microseconds later or so (Neunhäuserer 2010), transforms the
(quite dispersed) quantum probability law for x, into a
classical probability law for y. The CC interpretation I
consider, sees y coming so undetermined, then its value
directly picked by perception among not too unlikely
possibilities, ignoring the details of x and f it
may come from.
This clear but seldom recognized possibility, leaves
comparatively unattractive other mind/brain quantum links
proposals, usually involving quantum coherence, which moreover
lack empirical support (Sánchez-Cañizares). Beyond the fascinating
mysteriousness of QM for those lacking expertise, these may be of
two kinds. The ones see mind as a quantum computation, as if this
substantially differed from classical ones; but complexity
measures are the only real difference. Others like Stapp expect
quantum interference terms to serve as targets of perceptions by
the projection postulate; but this cannot rival the impact of a
direct choice of measurement result.
Thus, neurologists should take GSM as a foundation, to search for
the expression of free will in its probabilistic predictions,
these being the main form of quantum probabilities relevant for
biology. This interpretation of GSM is unpopular, as its classical
probabilistic formal structure (of mainly deterministic evolution
of random states) suggests a classical realistic interpretation.
A probabilistic theory like GSM being mathematical, poorly
represents, and cannot explain or generate, an ontological
semantics of potential or actual randomness, which is a conscious
experience. Such an interpretation requires pareidolia by a
conscious reader, and careful comparative likeliness analysis.
While admitting this substantial divide, (Epperson 2009) still
claimed the randomness semantics was dictated by the probabilistic
syntax (decoherence makes collapse). This assuming physicalism,
sounds as if the existence of stories encoded in the decimals of π
ensured their reality without the help of any conscious reader.
Now, this "decoherence interpretation" is generally rejected,
since the emergent and ambiguous nature of decoherence makes a
systematic collapse by decoherence inexpressible as a mathematical
law (Romano 2021; Sánchez-Cañizares).
Concerns for "realism" drives many philosophers and
experimentalists towards non-standard interpretations. Presuming
this to be a purely philosophical matter in their hands, they fail
to see what else than raw instrumentalism and poor philosophy
could be pushing physicists to standard ones instead.
Yet, they may be projecting onto these their own instrumentalist
view of mathematics: the philosophy gazed from the grand book
written in mathematical language (Galileo; Woit: blog articles),
could actually confirm the need to "shut up" and "investigate [the
world] without defining it!" (Feynman 1999), i.e. without
prejudices, to avoid wandering about in dark labyrinths of
hopeless research, or vain disputes in philosophical circles
playing with labels of "scientific realism" offset from the real
intellectual adventure of modern science.
Still, how could philosophers ignore the philosophical nonsense of fundamental probabilistic laws (unless probabilities were fractions, with denominator the number of branching realities from that event, while leaving no way to control branching numbers...) ? Already, the concept of absolute randomness is verificationally unclear (Barrett & Huttegger 2020). Probabilistic laws being shown fundamental for physics by mathematical insights, their metaphysical nonsense then suggests to dismiss the primitiveness of physics itself, and trace its "randomness" to a non-physical source.
Now, the consensus for the necessary acceptance of absolute randomness as evidence against free will in CC, is rivaled by the popularity of its necessary rejection as an argument for HV: in its name, random outputs described by standard QM as created in some nowhere located near measurement events, need an explanation as extracted from some pre-existing infinite random data pool (decimals of hidden variables) fancied from nowhere (without empirical or mathematical guidance), located really nowhere (fully non-local), and created at no time (to save its randomness from the label of indeterminism), namely at the birth of the universe where the breakdown of physics removes the need to explain the origin and meaningfulness of this deterministic fundamental randomness. It may not be hard to fill this pool with the decimals of π or a Chaitin constant, but it would still increase this picture's under-determined complexity.
Admittedly, physics is not killing people's freedom to believe
that free will does not exist if they really want to, insensitive
as they may be to any less than trivially absolute evidence from a
mathematical physics foreign to their minds. Philosophers appear
unclear with arguments, skeptically reviewing buzzwords like
"simplicity" given their own failures misapplying such criteria.
Let us complete our initial questions list (X= time
theory, Y= full laws) with:
H= fundamental substances list, selected from candidates :
two understandable ones (consciousness and mathematics); some
mysterious other, "physical" or anyhow "neutral".
Z= visible laws, with answer QM+RG. Generally, either Y=Z,
or Y completes Z by hidden details.
Assessing the likeliness of answers involves studying their
links, which needs to start by picturing their expected causal
order.
The randomness argument against free will seems to treat Y
as caused by Z. Similarly, the causal closure argument
seems to treat H as causally affected by Y. Such
causalities would look very strange. Now, if H comes as a
primitive independent fact, which then drives its
likeliness-ordered list of possible Y, from which Z
is finally extracted, then neither argument seems logical anymore.
Bayesian inference allows to assess the posterior probability P(H|E)
of an hypothesis H coming as a cause of a known fact
(evidence) E, as proportional to P(E|H).P(H),
where the prior probability P(H) of H is a
matter of taste, and arguments should focus on assessing the
probability P(E|H) of E given H.
Our findings on the ontological structures (X) of
mathematics and consciousness, coincide with the expectable
picture if both are primitive: they are similar but independent.
Physics confirms this by providing theoretical physics as a no
time's land between them (its "time" not being ontological).
It seems hard to choose a H without consciousness, with
either the mathematical, the physical or both, and to explain
their difference. Mathematical Platonism seems hardly resistible,
both a priori (Duncan 2014), and a posteriori by the
indispensability argument (Schneider 2017), given the high-level
style of mathematics involved in theoretical physics (Woit 2015).
Since physical structures appear contained by mathematical ones,
a mathematical monism can be tried. Our world would then appear as
an emerging tower of multiple ontological concepts with different
structures over the same substance. On top of the mysteriously
downplayed set theoretical ontology, the physical would emerge
first, then generate the strangely prominent conscious ontology
over finite mathematical systems. Brain states being finitely
complex like any local physical state, can in principle be encoded
as natural numbers. Then, morality consists in giving conscious
existence to more happy numbers than sad ones.
But, starting with a pure concept of physical or mathematical
reality, how natural and plausible would be the spontaneous
emergence of this ontological tower ?
"In fact, one might argue that if one was to design elegant laws of physics that allow a role for the conscious mind, one could not do much better than the bipartite dynamics of standard quantum mechanics: one principle governing deterministic evolution in normal cases, and one principle governing nondeterministic evolution in special situations that have a prima facie link to the mental." (Chalmers 2003: 9, p.31)
To argue otherwise, requires to invent laws fitting better than
QM all the needs for comfortable mind-matter interactions. Quantum
macro-coherence would not be better. The famous "interaction
problem" proceeds in the opposite way, defeating its claimed
conclusion.
Precisely, if consciousness escapes mathematics, then
mathematical laws for physics must provide clothes for the causal
influence of "what cannot be described", either in choice of
outcome or in time of intervention. Therefore, the literal
muteness of physics about the source of measurement outcomes, is
itself, on another level, the clearest expectable message, by its
way of perfectly matching this requirement.
The one worthy objection I foresee, is to ask : under
spiritualism, why does reality need to appear physical, following
any mathematical law ? The answer, from spiritual sources, is that
it doesn't : as big as our universe is, even with multiple reality
branches, it is neither the first nor the main kind of reality
system created by consciousness. As any individual is special, any
reality system can also be special. Ours is special by its
physical appearance, providing a kind of experience not found in
other reality systems. But, it only needs to seem physical in
practice; it neither needs nor happens to keep looking so all the
way down under detailed analysis.
Allori, Valia (2016),
"Primitive Ontology and the Classical World" In R. Kastner, J.
Jeknic-Dugic & G. Jaroszkiewicz (eds.), Quantum
Structural Studies: Classical Emergence from the Quantum Level.
World Scientific. pp. 175-199, <https://philpapers.org/rec/ALLPOA-3>
Anta, J. (2021). "The epistemic schism of statistical
mechanics". THEORIA. An International Journal for Theory,
History and Foundations of Science, 36(3), 399–419.
<https://doi.org/10.1387/theoria.22134>
Arenhart, Jonas R. Becker (2019), "Bridging the Gap Between
Science and Metaphysics, with a Little Help from Quantum
Mechanics", Proceedings of the 3rd Filomena Workshop /
João Daniel Dantas, Evelyn Erickson, Sanderson Molick (editores).
– Natal: PPGFIL, 2019. ISBN: 978-85-66377-10-1. <https://philarchive.org/archive/ROCTSC>
Arroyo, Raoni Wohnrath (2020), "Discussions on physics,
metaphysics and metametaphysics: Interpreting quantum mechanics",
PhD thesis. <https://repositorio.ufsc.br/handle/123456789/216278>
Arroyo, Raoni Wohnrath & Arenhart, Jonas R. Becker (2020),
"Floating free from physics: the metaphysics of quantum
mechanics", <https://arxiv.org/abs/2012.05822>
Arroyo, Raoni Wohnrath (2022), "Consciousness and quantum
mechanics: a philosophical approach". In Portuguese. To be
published at NEL/UFSC. <arXiv:2201.09663>
Barrett, Jeffrey A. (2006), "A quantum mechanical argument for
mind–body dualism", Erkenntnis, 65(1): 97-115, <http://www.socsci.uci.edu/~jabarret/bio/publications/quantum%20argument%20for%20dualism.pdf>
Barrett, Jeffrey A. (2018), "Everett’s Relative-State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics", Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, <https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-everett/>
Barrett, Jeffrey A. & Huttegger, Simon (2020) "Quantum Randomness and Underdetermination" [Preprint] <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/16905/>
Bennett, Karen (2021), "Why I am not a dualist", Oxford
Studies in Philosophy of Mind Volume 1, <https://philpapers.org/rec/BENWIA>
Briggs, Rachael & Forbes, Graeme A (2012), "The Real Truth
about the Unreal Future". Oxford Studies in Metaphysics,
7. <https://philpapers.org/rec/BRITRT-2>
(The Real Truth About the Unreal Future,
2011)
Briggs, Rachael & Forbes, Graeme A (2017), "The Growing-Block: just
one thing after another?", Philosophical Studies 174
(4):927-943,<https://kar.kent.ac.uk/55844/>
Bryant, Amanda (2020), "Keep the chickens cooped: the epistemic
inadequacy of free range metaphysics", Synthese 197
(5):1867-1887, <https://philpapers.org/rec/BRYKTC-2>
Burns, Jean E. (2012), "The Action of Consciousness and the
Uncertainty Principle", Journal of Nonlocality 1 (1), <https://journals.sfu.ca/jnonlocality/index.php/jnonlocality/article/view/9>
Callender, Craig (2011a), "Time's Ontic Voltage", in Adrian
Bardon (ed.), The future of the philosophy of time. London, UK:
Routledge. pp. 73-94, <https://www.craigcallender.com/publications>
Callender, Craig (2011b), "Philosophy of Science and Metaphysics", The Bloomsbury Companion to the Philosophy of Science, French and Saatsi, <https://www.craigcallender.com/publications>
Callender, Craig (2018),"Can We Quarantine the Quantum Blight?", Scientific Realism and the Quantum (OUP), 2020, edited by Saatsi and French. <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/15450/>
Carballo-Rubio et al., "Inner horizon instability and the
unstable cores of regular black holes", Journal of High Energy
Physics 2021(5), <https://arxiv.org/abs/2101.05006>
Chalmers, D. (2003), "Consciousness and its place in nature". In
Stephen P. Stich & Ted A. Warfield (eds.), Blackwell Guide
to the Philosophy of Mind. Blackwell. pp. 102--142 <http://consc.net/papers/nature.pdf>
Chalmers, D. (2017), "Idealism and the Mind-Body Problem", in (W.
Seager, ed.) The Routledge Handbook to Panpsychism
(Routledge, 2018), <https://philpapers.org/rec/CHAIAT-11>
Chalmers, D. & McQueen, Kelvin J. (2021), "Consciousness and
the Collapse of the Wave Function", Forthcoming in (S. Gao, ed.) Consciousness
and Quantum Mechanics (Oxford University Press), arXiv:2105.02314
[quant-ph].
Chen, Eddy Keming (2020) "Bell’s Theorem, Quantum Probabilities, and Superdeterminism", Eleanor Knox and Alastair Wilson (eds.), The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Physics, <arXiv:2006.08609>
De Caro, Mario & Putnam, Hilary (2020), "Free Will and
Quantum Mechanics", The Monist, Volume 103, Issue 4, Pages
415–426, doi: 10.1093/monist/onaa014
,<https://www.researchgate.net/publication/346737990>
Del Santo, Flavio (2020), "Indeterminism, causality and
information: Has physics ever been deterministic?", arXiv:2003.07411
[physics.hist-ph]
Dilley, Frank B. (2004), "Taking consciousness seriously: A
defense of Cartesian dualism", International Journal for
Philosophy of Religion 55:135–153, Kluwer Academic
Publishers. <https://philpapers.org/rec/DILTCS>
Duncan, Steven M. (2011), "Determinism and Luck", <https://philpapers.org/rec/DUNDAL>
Duncan, Steven M. (2014) "Platonism by the Numbers", <https://philarchive.org/rec/DUNPBT>
Durieux, Jude Arnout (2021), "Freedom in a physical world", <https://philarchive.org/rec/DURFIA>
Epperson, Michael (2009), "Quantum Mechanics and Relational Realism: Logical Causality and Wave Function Collapse", Process studies 38 (2): 340–367. <https://scholarlypublishingcollective.org/uip/ps/article/38/2/340/212404>
Everett, Hugh (1957), «"Relative state" formulation of quantum
mechanics», Reviews of Modern Physics 29 (3):454--462,
<http://www.weylmann.com/relative_state.pdf>
Feynman, R. (1999), The Pleasure of Finding Things Out
ch.9 (interview by Omni), Perseus Books.
Fraser, Doreen (2020) "The Development of Renormalization Group
Methods for Particle Physics: Formal Analogies Between Classical
Statistical Mechanics and Quantum Field Theory". Synthese
197 (7):3027-3063. <https://philpapers.org/rec/FRATDO-31>
Galileo (1623), The Assayer.
Goetz, Stewart (2021), "Libertarian Free Will, Naturalism, and Science", Journal of Philosophical Theological Research, <http://pfk.qom.ac.ir/article_2034.html>
Hamilton, Andrew J. S. (2018), "Towards a general description of the interior structure of rotating black holes", arXiv:1108.3512 [gr-qc]
Hamilton, Andrew J. S. & McMaken, Tyler (2021), "Geometry
near the inner horizon of a rotating, accreting black hole",
Phys. Rev. D 103, 084014, arXiv:2102.10402
Hoffman, D.D. et al (2018), "Conscious agents networks: Formal analysis and application to cognition". Cognitive Systems Research, 47, 186-213. <https://www.cogsci.uci.edu/~ddhoff/CA-circuits-CSR-rev.pdf>
Kastrup, B. (2017), "On the Plausibility of Idealism: Refuting
Criticisms", Disputatio 9 (44):13-34, <https://philpapers.org/rec/KASOTP-3>
Kastrup, B. (2019), «Reasonable Inferences From Quantum
Mechanics: A Response to “Quantum Misuse in Psychic Literature”»,
Journal of Near-Death Studies, 37(3), <https://philarchive.org/rec/KASRIF>
Le Bihan, Baptiste (2014), "No-Futurism and Metaphysical Contingentism", Axiomathes 24 (4):483-497, <https://philpapers.org/rec/LEBNAM>
Lewis, Peter J. (2006), "Conspiracy Theories of Quantum
Mechanics", The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,
Vol. 57, Nr 2, <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/2651/>
Loss, Roberto (2019) "No Ground for Doomsday". Inquiry: An
Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (9-10):1136-1156.
<https://philpapers.org/rec/LOSNGF>
Lycan, William G. (2009), "Giving Dualism its Due",
Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87:4, 551-563, DOI:
10.1080/00048400802340642
Malozemoff, Alexis P. & Mroczkowski, Jack A. (2019),
"Quantum Misuse in Psychic Literature: A Rejoinder" (abstract), Journal
of Near-Death Studies, Volume 37, Number 3, Spring 2019;
University of North Texas Libraries, UNT Digital Library, Durham,
North Carolina. <https://digital.library.unt.edu/ark:/67531/metadc1752581/>
McCoy, Barry M. (1994), "The Connection Between Statistical Mechanics and Quantum Field Theory", arXiv:hep-th/9403084
McQueen (2015), Kelvin J., "Four Tails Problems for Dynamical
Collapse Theories", Studies in the History and Philosophy of
Modern Physics 49:10-18, arXiv:1501.05778
[quant-ph]
Merricks, Trenton (2006), "Good-Bye Growing Block”, Oxford
Studies in Metaphysics (vol. 2, Oxford University Press),
<https://www.trentonmerricks.com/public/publications/Growing-Block.pdf>
Mohammadian, M (2021), "If Consciousness Causes Collapse, the
Zombie Argument Fails", Synthese 199, 1599–1615 (2021),
<https://philpapers.org/rec/MOHICC>
Moore (2021), D.
"Libertarian Free Will and the Physical Indeterminism Luck
Objection". Philosophia.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00370-2, <https://philpapers.org/rec/MOOLFW>
Myrvold, Wayne C. (2018) "Ontology for Collapse Theories", in Shan Gao, ed., The Collapse of the Wave Function (Cambridge University Press, 2018), 97–123. <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/13318/>
Neunhäuserer, J. (2010), "Dynamics, Quantum mechanics and the
Indeterminism of nature", <https://philpapers.org/rec/NEUDQM>)
Reason, Catherine M (2017), "Comment on the paper Quantum mechanics needs no consciousness by Yu and Nikolic (2011)", arXiv:1707.01346 [quant-ph]
Roberts, Jane (1970). The Seth Material (ch. 18, or Early
Sessions book 9, sessions 426-427). Reprinted, 2001 by New
Awareness Network. Quoted at <settheory.net/seth-creation>.
-- (1972), Seth Speaks: The Eternal Validity of the Soul.
Amber-Allen Publishing (reprinted 1994), <https://stormwolfwords.files.wordpress.com/2014/05/seth-speaks.pdf>
--- (1979). The Nature of the Psyche: Its Human Expression. Prentice-Hall, Amber-Allen Publishing (Reprinted 1996), Session 797: "Your universe...beside the point", <http://lukaali.com/seth/THE%20NATURE%20OF%20THE%20PSYCHE.html>.
Rodrigues, José Gusmão (2014), "There are no good objections to
substance dualism". Philosophy, 89, Issue 2, pp. 199-222
doi:10.1017/S0031819114000060
Romano, Davide (2021), "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of
Decoherence", Quantum Mechanics and Fundamentality (V.
Allori, ed.), Synthese Library. <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/19125/>
Runyan, Jason D. (2018), "Agent-‐causal libertarianism,
statistical neural laws and wild coincidences", Synthese
195 (10):4563-4580 <https://philarchive.org/rec/RUNALS>
Sánchez-Cañizares, Javier (2014), "The Mind-Brain Problem and the Measurement Paradox of Quantum Mechanics: Should We Disentangle Them?" (removed from: NeuroQuantology 2014, Vol. 12, 1: 76-95), <https://www.researchgate.net/publication/262104515>; short version: "Is Quantum Physics Relevant for the Mind-Brain Problem?" (2015), <https://www.researchgate.net/publication/286623445>
Schneider, Susan (2017) "Does the Mathematical Nature of Physics Undermine Physicalism?" Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24, (9–10):7-39.
Sepetyi, Dmytro (2018), "Quantum Mechanics and Consciousness: No
Evidence for Idealism", ISSN 2522-9338. Філософська думка,
2018, № 4, <https://www.researchgate.net/publication/327594187_Quantum_Mechanics_and_Consciousness_No_Evidence_for_Idealism>
Smythe, T. W. (2017). "Defending Dualism". Advances in Social
Sciences Research Journal, 4(7) 51-58.
DoI:10.14738/assrj.47.2964.
Soltau, Andrew (2009), "Times two: The tenses of linear and
collapse dynamics in relational quantum mechanics", <https://philpapers.org/rec/SOLTTT>
--- (2010), "logical types in quantum mechanics", <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/5554/>
--- (2018), "The Quantum-Mechanical Frame of Reference Part 2:
Logical Type in Time Evolution" sections 6-8,
DOI:10.13140/RG.2.2.10990.87363, <https://www.researchgate.net/publication/330016514>
Squires, Euan (1986). The Mystery of the Quantum World.
Hilger. pp. 72–73.
Sundberg, Christian, "PRE-BIRTH EXPERIENCE: Life Before Birth,
The Spirit of God, Choice & The Veil" from 13:03, Passion
Harvest Youtube channel, Mar 13, 2021, <youtu.be/sEYvYX7Tcmk&t=783s>
van Lommel, P. (2019), «Quantum Physics as Analogy: A Response to
“Quantum Misuse in Psychic Literature”»; Journal of Near-Death
Studies, 37(3); 174-184, <https://pimvanlommel.nl/wp-content/uploads/2020/11/Quantum-Physics-as-Analogy-response-article-JNDS-2019.pdf>
Wallace, D. (2007), "The Quantum Measurement Problem: State of Play", D. Rickles (ed), The Ashgate Companion to the New Philosophy of Physics (Ashgate, 2008), <https://arxiv.org/abs/0712.0149>
Wallace, D. (2016a), "Lessons from Realistic Physics for the
Metaphysics of Quantum Theory", Synthese 197, 4303-4818
(2020), <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/15293/1/quantum_metaphysics_revised%20v3.pdf>
Wallace, D. (2016b), "Probability and Irreversibility in Modern Statistical Mechanics: Classical and Quantum", To appear in D. Bedingham, O. Maroney and C. Timpson (eds.), Quantum Foundations of Statistical Mechanics (Oxford University Press, forthcoming), arXiv:2104.11223 [cond-mat.stat-mech]
Wallace, David (2018), "On the Plurality of Quantum Theories: Quantum theory as a framework, and its implications for the quantum measurement problem" (2018), S. French and J. Saatsi, Scientific Realism and the Quantum (OUP, 2020), <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/15292/1/leeds_realism.pdf>
Wallace, David (2019), "Review of R. Healey, 'The Quantum Revolution in Philosophy'", Analysis 80 (2020),<https://sites.pitt.edu/~dmw121/papers/healey_review.pdf>
Wallace, David (2020), "The Necessity of Gibbsian Statistical Mechanics" In V. Allori (ed.), Statistical Mechanics and Scientific Explanation: Determinism, Indeterminism and Laws of Nature (World Scientific). <http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/15290/>
Woit, Peter: blog articles
(2010) "Bohmian Spat" <www.math.columbia.edu/~woit/wordpress/?p=2914>
(2012) "’t Hooft on Cellular Automata and String Theory" <www.math.columbia.edu/~woit/wordpress/?p=5022>
(2018) "Beyond Weird" <www.math.columbia.edu/~woit/wordpress/?p=10522>
Woit, Peter (2015), "Towards a Grand Unified Theory of
Mathematics and Physics",
arXiv:1506.07576
[physics.hist-ph]